User:Non-pegasus/sandbox/Holism draft
This is not a Wikipedia article: It is an individual user's work-in-progress page, and may be incomplete and/or unreliable. For guidance on developing this draft, see Wikipedia:So you made a userspace draft. Find sources: Google (books · news · scholar · free images · WP refs) · FENS · JSTOR · TWL |
Holism is the interdisciplinary idea that systems possess properties as wholes apart from the properties of their component parts. [1][2][3] The concept of holism informs the methodology for a broad array of scientific fields and lifestyle practices. When applications of holism are said to reveal properties of a whole system beyond those of its parts, these qualities are referred to as emergent properties of that system. Holism in all contexts is opposed to reductionism which is the notion that systems containing parts contain no unique properties beyond those parts. Scientific proponents of holism consider the search for these emergent properties within systems the primary reason to incorporate it into scientific assumptions or perspective.[4]
Background
[edit]The term "holism" was coined by Jan Smuts (1870-1950) in his 1926 book Holism and Evolution.[5] While he never assigned a consistent meaning to the word, Smuts used holism to express at least three features of reality in general.[6] First, holism is the idea of an empirical whole system with examples including atomic or material systems, cells, and an individual's personality. Smuts used this notion is holism to suggest that concepts of body and mind, each systems in their own right, are not estranged from one another but form the holistic concept of a person. Second, that the process of evolution is neither mechanistic nor transcendent. Smuts criticized writers who emphasized Darwinian concepts of natural selection and genetic variation to support an accidental view of natural operations within the universe. In this way, holism is the tendency of a whole system to creatively respond to environmental stressors, a process in which parts naturally transcend themselves to bring the whole into more advanced states. Smuts used Pavlovian studies to show that efficient inheritance of behavioral changes supports the claim of creative evolution as opposed to purely mechanistic development in nature.[7][8] Smuts believed that this creative process was intrinstic within systems and ruled out indirect, transcendent forces.[5][9] Finally, Smuts uses holism to explain the concrete (nontranscendent) nature of the universe in general. In his words, holism is "the ultimate synthetic, ordering, organizing, regulative activity in the universe which accounts for all the structural groupings and syntheses in it."[10] Smuts concepts of holism come together to argue that a holistic view of the universe explains its processes and their evolution more effectively than a reductive view.
Professional philosophers of science and linguistics did not consider Holism and Evolution seriously and the work has received criticism for a lack of theoretical coherence.[5][9][11] Biological scientists, however, did offer favorable assessments shortly after its initial print in 1926.[12] Over time, the meaning of the word holism became most closely associated with Smuts first conception of the term, yet without any metaphysical commitments to monism, dualism, or similar concepts which can be interpreted from Smuts' work.[13]
Scientific applications
[edit]Physics
[edit]Nonseparability
[edit]The advent of holism in the 20th century coincided with the gradual development of quantum mechanics. Holism in physics refers to the nonseparability of physical systems from their parts, especially quantum phenomena. Classical physics cannot be regarded as holistic, as the behavior of individual parts represents the whole. However, the state of a system in quantum theory resists reductive analysis. Two spacially separated quantum systems are described as entangled, or nonseparable, from each other when a meaningful analysis of one system is indistinguishable from that of the other.[14] There are different conceptions of nonseparability in physics and its exploration is considered to broadly present insight into the ontological problem.[14][15]
Variants
[edit]In one sense, holism for physics is a perspective about the best way to understand the nature of a physical system. In this sense, holism is the methodological claim that systems are accurately understood according to their properties as a whole. A methodological reductionist in physics might seek to explain, for example, the behavior of a liquid by examining its component molecules, atoms, ions or electrons. A methodological holist, on the other hand, believes there is something misguided about this approach; one proponent, a condensed matter physicist, puts it: “the most important advances in this area come about by the emergence of qualitatively new concepts at the intermediate or macroscopic levels—concepts which, one hopes, will be compatible with one’s information about the microscopic constituents, but which are in no sense logically dependent on it.”[16] This perspective is considered a conventional attitude among contemporary physicists.[14] In another sense, holism is a metaphysical claim that the nature of a system is not determined by the properties of its component parts. There are three varieties of this sense of physical holism.
- Ontological holism: some systems are not merely composed of their physical parts
- Property holism: some systems have properties independent of their physical parts
- Nomological holism: some systems follow physical laws beyond the laws followed by their physical parts
The metaphysical claim does not assert that physical systems involve abstract properties beyond the composition of its physical parts, but that there are concrete properties aside from those of its basic physical parts. For instance, theoretical physicist David Bohm (1917-1992) supports this view head-on. Bohm believed that a complete description of the universe would have to go beyond a simple list of all its particles and their positions, there would also have to be a physical quantum field associated with the properties of those particles guiding their trajectories.[17] [18] Bohm's ontological holism concerning the nature of whole physical systems was literal.[19] But Niels Bohr, on the other hand, held ontological holism from an epistemological angle, rather than a literal one.[20] Bohr (1885-1962) saw an observational apparatus to be a part of a system under observation, besides the basic physical parts themselves. His theory agrees with Bohm that whole systems were not merely composed of their parts and it identifies properties such as position and momentum as those of whole systems beyond those of its components.[21] But Bohr states that these holistic properties are only meaningful in experimental contexts when physical systems are under observation and that these systems, when not under observation, cannot be said to have meaningful properties, even if these properties took place outside our observation. While Bohr claims these holistic properties exist only insofar as they can be observed, Bohm took his ontological holism one step further by claiming these properties must exist regardless.
Linguistics
[edit]Meaning holism, also known as semantic holism, approaches holism by suggesting that the meaning of individual words depends on the meaning of other words within a large web of other words. In general, meaning holism states that the properties which determine the meaning of a word are connected such that if the meaning of one word changes, the meaning of every other word in the web changes as well.[22][23] The set of words that alter in meaning due to a change in the meaning of some other is not necessarily specified in meaning holism, but typically such a change is taken straightforwardly to affect the meaning of every word in the language.[24][25][26][27]
In scientific disciplines, reductionism is the opposing viewpoint to holism. But in the context of linguistics or the philosophy of language, reductionism is typically referred to as atomism. Specifically, atomism states that each word's meaning is independent and so there are no emergent properties within a language. Additionally, there is meaning molecularism which states that a change in one word alters the meaning of only a relatively small set of other words.
The linguistic perspective of meaning holism is traced back to Quine[28] but was subsequently formalized by analytic philosophers Michael Dummett, Jerry Fodor, and Ernest Lepore.[29] While this holistic approach attempts to resolve a classical problem for the philosophy of language concerning how words convey meaning, there is debate over its validity mostly from two angles of criticism: opposition to compositionality and, especially, instability of meaning. The first claims that meaning holism conflicts with the compositionality of language. Meaning in some languages is compositional in that meaning comes from the structure of an expression's parts.[30][31] Meaning holism suggests that the meaning of words plays an inferential role in the meaning of other words: "pet fish" might infer a meaning of "less than 3 ounces." Since holistic views of meaning assume meaning depends on which words are used and how those words infer meaning onto other words, rather than how they are structured, meaning holism stands in conflict with compositionalism and leaves statements with potentially ambiguous meanings.[32][33] The second criticism claims that meaning holism makes meaning in language unstable. If some words must be used to infer the meaning of other words, then in order to communicate a message, the sender and the receiver must share an identical set of inferential assumptions or beliefs. If these beliefs were different, meaning may be lost.[34][35]
Many types of communication would be directly affected by the principles of meaning holism such as informative communication,[34] language learning,[36][37][38] and communication about psychological states.[39][40] Nevertheless, some meaning holists maintain that the instability of meaning holism is an acceptable feature from several different angles.[14] In one example, contextual holists make this point simply by suggesting we often do not actually share identical inferential assumptions but instead rely on context to counter differences of inference and support communication.[41]
Biology
[edit]Scientific applications of holism within biology are referred to as systems biology. The opposing analytical approach of systems biology is biological organization which models biological systems and structures only in terms of their component parts. "The reductionist approach has successfully identified most of the components and many of the interactions but, unfortunately, offers no convincing concepts or methods to understand how system properties emerge...the pluralism of causes and effects in biological networks is better addressed by observing, through quantitative measures, multiple components simultaneously and by rigorous data integration with mathematical models."[42] The objective in systems biology is to advance models of the interactions in a system. Holistic approaches to modelling have involved cellular modelling strategies[43], genomic interaction analysis[44], and phenotype prediction[45].
Systems medicine
[edit]Systems medicine is a practical approach to systems biology and accepts its holistic assumptions. Systems medicine takes the systems of the human body as made up of a complete whole and uses this as a starting point in its research and, ultimately, treatment.
Lifestyle applications
[edit]The term holism is also sometimes used in the context of various lifestyle practices, such as dieting, education, and healthcare, to refer to ways of life that either supplement or replace conventional practices. In these contexts, holism is not necessarily a rigorous or well-defined methodology for obtaining a particular lifestyle outcome. It is sometimes simply an adjective used to describe practices which take into account factors that standard forms of these practices may sometimes discound, especially in the context of alternative medicine.
See also
[edit]References
[edit]- ^ Seevnick, M.P. (2004), Holism, physical theories and quantum mechanicse, ScienceDirect.
- ^ Jackman, Henry, Meaning Holism, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition)
- ^ Julian Tudor Hart (2010) The Political Economy of Health Care pp.106, 258
- ^ David Deutsch (14 April 2011). The Fabric of Reality. Penguin Books Limited. ISBN 978-0-14-196961-9.
- ^ a b c Brush, Francis W. (1984), "4.1", Jan Christian Smuts and His Doctrine of Holism, Univ of Toronto Press
- ^ Hancock, W.K. (1962), Smuts 1. The Sanguine Years, 1870-1919, Cambridge Univ Press, p. 291
- ^ L. Getz, A.L. Kirkengen, E. Ulvestad, Menneskets biologi - mettet med erfaring, Tidsskr. Den Nor. Laegeforening. 7 (2011) 683–687. doi:10.4045/tidsskr.10.0874.
- ^ P. Jensen, Transgenerational epigenetic effects on animal behaviour, Prog. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 113 (2013) 447–454. doi:10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2013.01.001.
- ^ a b Jörgenfelt, Chris (2019), A critical analysis of J.C. Smuts’ theory of holism (PDF), European Journal of Integrative Medicine, Elsevier
- ^ Smuts, J.C. 1926. Holism and Evolution. P. 317. New York: The Macmillan Company.
- ^ Shelley, Christopher (2005), Jan Smuts and Personality Theory: The Problem of Holism in Psychology (PDF), University of Cape Town
{{citation}}
: line feed character in|title=
at position 34 (help) - ^ C.L. Morgan, Holism and Evolution by J. C. Smuts [Review], J. Philos. Stud. 2 (1927) 93–97. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3745387
- ^ Cite error: The named reference
OriginalDoctine
was invoked but never defined (see the help page). - ^ a b c d Healey, Richard; Gomes, Henrique (2022), "Holism and Nonseparability in Physics", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University
- ^ Karakostas, Vassilios (2004), Forms of Quantum Nonseparability and Related Philosophical Consequences (PDF), Journal for General Philosophy of Science
- ^ Leggett, A. J., 1987, p.113, The Problems of Physics, New York: Oxford University Press.
- ^ Bohm, D., 1980, Wholeness and the Implicate Order, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- ^ Bohm, D. and Hiley, B.J., 1993, The Undivided Universe, New York: Routledge.
- ^ B. J. Hiley: Some remarks on the evolution of Bohm's proposals for an alternative to quantum mechanics, 30 January 2010.
- ^ Faye, Jan, "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/qm-copenhagen/.
- ^ Bohr, N., 1934, Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- ^ Jackman, Henry, "Meaning Holism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/meaning-holism/>.
- ^ Hempel, C.G., 1950, “Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning”, Revue internationale de Philosophie, 41(11): 41–63.
- ^ Block, N., 1986, “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy (Studies in the Philosophy of Mind), 10: 615–678.
- ^ Field, H., 1977, “Logic, Meaning and Conceptual Role”, The Journal of Philosophy, LXXIV(7): 379–409.
- ^ Harman, G., 1993, “Meaning Holism Defended”, in Fodor and Lepore 1993, pp. 163–171.
- ^ Sellars, W., 1974, “Meaning as Functional Classification”, Synthese, 27: 417–37.
- ^ Quine, W.V., 1951, “Two dogmas of empiricism”, reprinted in W.V. Quine, 1953, From a logical point of view, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 20–46
- ^ Fodor, J. & E. Lepore 1992, Holism: A Shoppers Guide, Cambridge: Blackwell.
- ^ Fodor, J. & E. Lepore 1992, Holism: A Shoppers Guide, Cambridge: Blackwell.
- ^ Fodor, J. & E. Lepore 2002, The Compositionality Papers, New York: Oxford University Press.
- ^ Fodor, J. & E. Lepore 1992, Holism: A Shoppers Guide, Cambridge: Blackwell.
- ^ Pagin, P., 1997, “Is Compositionality Compatible with Holism?” Mind & Language, 12(1): 11–33.
- ^ a b Jackman, Henry, "Meaning Holism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/meaning-holism/>
- ^ Jackman, Henry, "Meaning Holism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL =<https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning-holism/notes.html#note-16>
- ^ Dummett, M., 1976, “What is a Theory of Meaning? (II)”, reprinted in M. Dummett, The Seas of Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996, 44
- ^ Dresner, E., 2002, “Holism, Language Acquisition and Algebraic Logic”, Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(4): 419–52.
- ^ Jönsson, M., 2014, “Semantic Holism and Language Learning”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43: 725–59.
- ^ Fodor, J., 1987, Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: MIT Press.
- ^ Fodor, J. & E. Lepore, 1992, Holism: A Shoppers Guide, Cambridge: Blackwell.
- ^ Bilgrami, A. 1992, Belief and Meaning, Oxford: Blackwell.
- ^ Sauer, Uwe; Heinemann, Matthias; Zamboni, Nicola (27 April 2007). "Genetics: Getting Closer to the Whole Picture". Science. 316 (5824): 550–551. doi:10.1126/science.1142502. PMID 17463274. S2CID 42448991.
- ^ Snoep, Jacky L; Westerhoff, Hans V (2005). "From isolation to integration, a systems biology approach for building the Silicon Cell". In Alberghina, Lilia; Westerhoff, Hans V (eds.). Systems Biology: Definitions and Perspectives. Topics in Current Genetics. Vol. 13. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. pp. 13–30. doi:10.1007/b106456. ISBN 978-3-540-22968-1.
- ^ Chiara Romualdi; Gerolamo Lanfranchi (2009). "Statistical Tools for Gene Expression Analysis and Systems Biology and Related Web Resources". In Stephen Krawetz (ed.). Bioinformatics for Systems Biology (2nd ed.). Humana Press. pp. 181–205. doi:10.1007/978-1-59745-440-7_11. ISBN 978-1-59745-440-7.
- ^ Karr, Jonathan R.; Sanghvi, Jayodita C.; Macklin, Derek N.; Gutschow, Miriam V.; Jacobs, Jared M.; Bolival, Benjamin; Assad-Garcia, Nacyra; Glass, John I.; Covert, Markus W. (July 2012). "A Whole-Cell Computational Model Predicts Phenotype from Genotype". Cell. 150 (2): 389–401. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2012.05.044. PMC 3413483. PMID 22817898.
External links
[edit]- Media related to Non-pegasus/sandbox/Holism draft at Wikimedia Commons